(单词翻译:单击)
To this last lecture of the present course, it seems to me desirable that I should briefly3 notice some assertions or suggestions, not uncommonly4 heard in the present day, that the great evils of war might be abated5 by the adoption6 of principles of action not necessarily identical with those which have been discussed in previous lectures. I pass over general statements which seem to me to be mere7 calumnies8, such as the charge against influential9 military men, that in every society they do their utmost to encourage the spirit of belligerency. Those who have had the privilege of acquaintance with famous soldiers will bear me out in saying that, while there is no class of men more humane10, there is none distinguished11 by a deeper dislike or hatred12 of war, however they may believe it to be inevitable13. But another assertion frequently made is much more respectable, and contains a larger proportion of truth. War, it is said, is irreconcilable14 with Christian15 belief and Christian practice. If men acted up to the standards of conduct which great numbers of them theoretically accept, there would be few wars or none. This has long been the doctrine16 of a sect17 whose various services to humanity I have already gratefully commemorated18 —— the Quakers; and also of an obscurer community, the Mennonites. It will be evident, I think, to everybody who bestows19 some careful thought on the subject, that there would be great difficulty in adapting a system which professes20 to regulate the relations of individual men with one another, to the relations of groups of men, of states; and in point of fact the Quakers have not always been quite consistent in the application of their principle. The Quakers of the colony of Pennsylvania were in the American War of Independence strong partisans21 of the colonial cause; and Benjamin Franklin has left us some curious stories of the fictions by which the Pennsylvanian Quakers reconciled their conscientious22 objections to war with their keen desire to assist the colonial troops. But it is proper to observe that this opinion of the unlawfulness of war has, in the course of ecclesiastical history, seemed several times likely to become the opinion of the whole Christian Church, or of a large portion of it. We have most of us been taught to believe, on the authority of a well-known passage in Tertullian, that the Roman Imperial armies were full of Christian soldiers; but the passage is inconsistent with others in the same writer; and I have seen a long catena of extracts from patristic authorities, extending from Justin Martyr24 to Jerome and Cyril, in which the inconsistency of the military profession with Christian belief is maintained. In fact, this became one of the main points of contention25 between Christians26 and pagans. The contention of Celsus, that the Christians refuse to bear arms even in cases of necessity, is met by Origen with the admission that the fact is so, but with the argument that the Christians do not go on campaigns with the Emperor because they serve him with their prayers. If these opinions did not become those of the whole Church, the cause must probably be sought in the course of historical events, for the invading Teutonic tribes who spread over the Empire could not be untaught the art and practice of fighting, even when they accepted some form of Christianity. Passing over a long space of time to the beginning of the modern history of Christianity, it seemed not improbable that the unlawfulness of war would become a doctrine of all the Protestant sects27; among theologians not quite estranged28 from Catholicity, the great Erasmus wrote as strongly of the wickedness of war as any Quaker of our day could do, and Sir Thomas More charged Luther and his followers29 with wishing to deprive sovereigns of their authority by denying to them the power of resistance. On the other hand, the writers dealt with in the foregoing lectures, the founders31 of International Law, did not adopt the opinion of the Lawfulness23 of war, though they were nearly all Protestants. Grotius argues vehemently32 against it, chiefly on Scriptural grounds. I take the fact to be that he and his immediate33 followers conceived the body of rules which they believed themselves to have rescued from neglect to be more serviceable for the purpose of regulating the concerns of nations in war and peace, than any system which pretended to a direct descent from Christian records or Christian tradition. The Law of Nature which they spoke34 of, and apparently35 believed in, with as little hesitation36 as if they were thinking of the English Common Law, has not stood against the assaults of modern criticism, and specially37 not against the inferences suggested by the modern study of primitive38 mankind. But it did prove possible to apply the rules associated with it to human societies in peace and war; whereas, though a general belief that war Divas unrighteous would assuredly have had important effects, nobody can say confidently what those effects would have been, or can assert that they would have included the extension and stability of peace. Another sweeping39 proposal for the virtual abolition40 of war, one of a very different order, however, from that just considered by me, must have come under the notice of most of us. It is said that there is always an alternative to a contest in arms. Nations fight because they cannot go to law. The old idea that the disputes of states are referred by war to a supernatural arbitrament is now abandoned; but though there is no international tribunal which can entertain as of right the controversies41 of nations, there is a substitute for it in international arbitration42. Let, therefore, every dispute be referred to an arbitrator or to a body of arbitrators, and let civilised communities defer43 to the award with no more demur44 than they exhibit in submitting to the decision of a court of justice. A belief in this remedy for war is being widely extended in our day. It is held by persons worthy45 of ail46 respect and promoted by powerful voluntary associations. I should be the last person to deny that arbitration in international affairs has often been very happily applied47. Nations very often, like men, adhere to their view of disputed points more from pride of opinion than from any real interest in it. Some of these disputes, again, turn on questions of fact, which have not been solved because they have not been properly investigated, but which are easily disposed of when thus looked into by fresh and disc. passionate48 minds.
But before this or any other country commits itself to arbitration as a universal remedy for war, one or two of its defects ought to be specially noticed. In the first place, though arbitration in individual disputes is well known and frequently tried. it is very unlike the arbitration proposed by its advocates for international differences. The arbitration with which all lawyers are familiar, is merely a displacement49 of the structure of an ordinary court of justice. The parties agree to refer all or part of the matters in dispute between them to the decision of an arbitrator, who takes the place of the judge or of the judge and a jury, and they at the same time agree that his decision, unless impeachable50 on certain grounds of law, shall be enforced by the court as would be its own decree. It is a very convenient course when the questions of fact to be adjudicated upon are numerous and complicated, and the principal objection to it is that it is apt to be very expensive. What I wish to point out is that arbitration as in use between individuals in England does not exclude the one great feature of a court of justice, the force which underlies51 its operations. There are, no doubt, arbitrations52 which come nearer the arbitrations contemplated53 by the enthusiasts54 for universal arbitrations between disputant sovereigns. A skilful55 man of business in British commercial cities, an eminent56 specialist in the practical applications of science, will sometimes obtain a sort of celebrity57 for just and wise adjudication, and nothing like the process of a court is found necessary to secure obedience58 to his award. It is, however, many centuries since such authority was attributed to any man or class in international matters; the current of opinion in our day runs distinctly against the assumption that any exceptional knowledge is necessary for the solution of great political and international questions, and therefore the arbitration of which we hear so much would in the long run, and if tried on a great scale, prove to have the defects which would soon show themselves in a court of justice which the State had failed to invest with irresistible59 coercive power.
The want of coercive power is, in fact, the one important drawback which attends all attempts to improve International Law by contrivances imitated from the internal economy of states, by something like legislation, and by something like the administration of law by organised tribunals. Still, nobody who understands the subject, and has observed the course of events, will deny a certain measure of success to international arbitrations, and there is much reason to wish them an extended sphere. But there are some practical defects in them, as they stand, which should be observed upon, because they may possibly admit of being remedied. It is well known to English practicing lawyers that a certain class of litigants61 are, so to put it, unpopular in English courts, so that there is considerable difficulty in obtaining for them a full measure of justice. Among these, to give instances, are insurance companies, and
to some extent railway companies. In the same way there are states bringing their controversies before bodies of international arbitrators who are in the same sense unpopular litigants; and, if inquiry62 were practicable, I should not be surprised to find that, in the opinion of English diplomatists and statesmen in charge of our foreign affairs, our own country is not a Popular litigant60 in arbitrations. The truth is our country is thought to be very wealthy, and to be able to bear the burden of a money award against it better than any other community. It is believed to be comparatively careless of its foreign policy, and not to show much sensitiveness under a judicial63 rebuff. Lastly, there is a general impression that it has so contrived64 its international relations as to escape from its fair share of the anxieties and sufferings which fall upon other states through war, apprehension65 of war, and preparation for war.
Again, it is not, I think, to be denied that the composition of courts (if I may for the moment so style them) of international arbitration is not altogether satisfactory. An indispensable element in it is one or more of the class of lawyers who are commonly called jurists But this word has much changed its meaning. As lately as the last century there was a class of lawyers bearing this title who had made a special study of International Law, and whose collective opinion had serious influence on the development of the system. But in England the Ecclesiastical and Admiralty Courts have been transformed, and the special class of lawyers trained in Roman Civil Law who practiced in those courts has either disappeared or is on the point of disappearing. Nobody can quite say at present what a jurist is. The word is used in a number of new senses; and in point of fact most famous foreign writers on International Law are salaried functionaries66 of foreign chanceries, nor can any reader of very modern treatises67 on the subject fail to see that many of then1 are strongly affected68 by the official connection of the writer with his Government, and by his knowledge of the interest which he supposes that Government to have in the establishment, maintenance, or development of particular features of the international system. This last-mentioned drawback on the usefulness of international quasi-courts of arbitration, that in our day they are not always satisfactorily constituted, is closely connected with one general defect which at present characterizes them —— they do not exercise any continuous jurisdiction69, they are always formed for the single occasion. It is quite uncertain what weight is to be attached to the award of international arbitrators as a precedent70. The mode in which International Law makes progress in default of a regular Legislature is a very important subject, which I have not been able to take up in a manner worthy of it in the present course of lectures, but which I hope to enter upon at some future time. There is, however, no doubt that a quasi-judicial award, given on a serious occasion, and acquiesced71 in by powerful nations who were parties to the litigation, deeply and permanently72 affects the law. But quasi-courts of arbitrators, constituted ad hoc, of necessity attend simply to the question in immediate dispute, and do not weigh the opinion they give regarded as a precedent. They cannot look before and after —— to the entire history of the Law of Nations. This result of their defective73 structure is particularly conspicuous74 and particularly dangerous in what was perhaps the greatest of all arbitrations, that which settled the difference which had arisen between Great Britain and the United States as to liability for the depredations75 of Southern Confederate cruisers on Northern American shipping76. I have nothing to say against the value of the Geneva arbitration in regard to the particular occasion on which it was resorted to. It put an end to a number of bitterly disputed questions which had accumulated during the War of Secession, and which might have smouldered on for years, to the great danger of the whole civilised world. But the serviceableness of the Geneva award in its effects on International Law is much more questionable77. Even at the outset, the disputants are found arguing that the arbitrators should have regard to principles which one of them did not admit to be included in International Law. Great Britain protests against this principle, but nevertheless allows the arbitration to proceed. We may, however, be quite sure that if an analogous78 dispute should hereafter occur, this principle will be urged by any Power which has an interest in insisting upon it, and under any circumstances a grave uncertainty79 is introduced into International Law. But the Geneva decision, regarded as an international precedent, is open to much more serious objection than this. As is well known, Great Britain during the Confederate War was a neutral, and she was condemned81 by the arbitrators to pay very heavy damages as punishment for breaches83 of her duty as a neutral. She was penally84 dealt with for a number of acts and omissions85, each in itself innocent. She had a standard of due diligence applied to her neglects which was new and extremely severe. And generally she had a rule of neutral duty applied to her which, if it has been really engrafted on the Law of Nations, has changed that law materially for the worse. But if there be one thing more than another which a true court of international justice might be desired to keep in view in its decisions, it is their future effect on the rights of neutrals. Nothing tends to enlarge the area of maritime86 wars so much as the neglect of these rights. Nothing tends so much to make war intolerably oppressive as any rule which helps, beyond what is absolutely necessary, to invade the principle that neutral states are merely states which have kept out of a calamity87 which has fallen on others, and which merely desire to follow their own business in their own way. From this point of view, the result of the Geneva arbitration is not happy. It turns back pro1 tanto the drift of legal opinion on neutral fights, which for many years had been setting in another direction. The Geneva arbitration, I repeat, conferred great benefit for the moment on Great Britain and the United States. But, looked at as a precedent likely to exercise serious influence on the whole Law of Nations, I fear it was dangerous, as well as reactionary88 and retrogressive.
I have dwelt on this aspect of the Geneva arbitration because it puts in what appears to me a striking light the disadvantages which attend these expedients89 for settling international disputes, through their being invariably brought into action merely ad hoc. A true court of quasi-justice, like a court of municipal justice, would be sure to consider the effect of a given decision on the whole branch of law which it administers. The defect, however, appears to me to be one for which it would not be altogether impossible to find a remedy. Many, indeed, of the innovations which have been proposed for the cure of palpable infirmities in the application of our International Jurisprudence to facts seem to have but small chance of adoption, at any rate in a society of nations like that in which we live, through the magnitude of the sacrifices which they would impose on particular communities. But no appreciable90 sacrifice would have to be made by the single or corporate91 sovereigns of the civilised world if they were to agree to constitute a single permanent court, or board, or assemblage of arbitrators, who should act as referees92 in any questions which any community or communities should choose to submit to them. Such a court would not be free from the infirmity which afflicts93 all such additions to the international system. It would have no force at its back. But I think it would be better constituted. I think it would be more free from prejudice, and would soon be recognised as freer, than the present occasional adjudicators. And I think it could be better trusted to adjust its awards to the entire body of international principles, distinctions, and rules. Such a tribunal as I have described, a court, board, or commission of arbitrators, having a certain degree of permanence, might have all the advantages which I have described for it —— it might be better constituted for its purpose than are the bodies which are now trusted to conduct arbitrations, its awards might be better considered with regard to their effect on the entirety of the Law of Nations, and it might be employed more freely as a body of referees on critical questions which are now left to themselves for want of any authority to which their consideration might be committed. But still it would not be a true court of justice. It would share the characteristic, in modern eyes the weakness, of all International Law, that it cannot command the assistance of force. Its rules have no sanction. It cannot punish the breach82 of its rules or the violation94 of an international duty. It is true that a defiance95 of the Law of Nations sometimes draws down upon the offender96 a very serious sanction, though it is indirect. Few sovereigns or states remain unmoved by the disapprobation which an open breach of international obligation provokes disapprobation now rapidly diffused97 over the whole civilised world by the telegraph and the press. Nothing could be more satisfactory than the outburst of indignation which occurred in 1870, when the Russian Government took advantage of the difficulties in which Europe was placed by the war between Germany and France, to repudiate98 the restrictions99 under which Russia lay in respect of naval100 action in the Black Sea through the provisions of the Treaty of Paris, restrictions which, it must be confessed, were not wholly reasonable. The Russian Government had to abandon its position; and at a Conference of the representatives of Powers who had been signatories of the Treaty of Paris, it was declared that 'it is an essential principle of the Law of Nations that no Power can liberate101 itself from the engagement of a treaty, nor modify the stipulations thereof, unless with the consent of the contracting Powers by means of an amicable102 engagement.' It is true that this assertion of the virtual perpetuity of treaties (to which an exception must be introduced, save by the effect of war) contains a principle which is not without a danger of its own. But the receded103 principle is that which was laid down at the Conference. The truth is that an offender against the obligations of International Law is at present seriously weakened by the disapprobation he incurs104. Nobody knew this better than Napoleon Bonaparte, who, next perhaps to Frederick the Great, was the most perfidious105 sovereign in modern history, when he persistently106 endeavoured through his official scribes to fasten on this country the name of 'perfidious Albion.'
But after all qualifications have been allowed, the denial to International Law of that auxiliary107 force which is commanded by all municipal law, and by every municipal tribunal, is a most lamentable108 disadvantage. The system owes to it every sort of infirmity. Its efficiency and its improvement are alike hindered. And in the last resort, when two or more disputant Powers have wrought109 themselves to such a heat of passion that they are determined110 to fight, the rest of the civilised world, though persuaded that the contest is unnecessary and persuaded that its contagion111 will spread, has, in the present state of international relations, no popover of forbidding or punish ing the armed attacks of one state on another. The great majority of those entitled to have an opinion may condemn80 the threatened war, but there is no officer of the Law of Nations to interfere112 with the headlong combatants. The amount of force which is at the disposal of what is called the commonwealth113 of nations collectively is immense and practically irresistible, but it is badly distributed and not well directed, and it is too often impotent, not only for the promotion114 of good, but for the prevention of acknowledged evil.
About six months ago, when an Association which has been formed for the codification115 of the Law of Nations (which I may describe parenthetically as most excellent undertaking116) was holding its meetings, the subject attracted considerable, though only momentary117, attention. An eminent French economist118, M. de Molinari, published a proposal for what he called a League of Neutral Powers. The majority of civilised states are always neutral, though the neutrals are not always the same. If the neutrals combine they are irresistible, partly from their strength and partly from their power to make one of two belligerent119 Powers irresistible by joining its side. M. de Molinari's suggestion was that it should be one of the duties of neutrality to thwart120 the spirit of belligerency, to make it a rule that the outbreak of hostility121 between any two Powers should be a casus belli as regards the rest, and to embody122 these arrangements in the stipulations of a treaty. It is impossible to deny that if such a combination of neutral Powers could be effected under the suggested conditions it would be a most effectual safeguard against war, and this is in itself an ample justification123 for starting the proposal. But the objections to it are plain, and were at once advanced. If carried into effect, it might diminish the chances of war; but it takes for granted that the mechanism124 of war will remain unimpaired. If neutrals are to be equal to their new duties, they must maintain great armies and navies on the modern scale, or they may not be able to cope with the contemplated emergency. Thus, though the risk of war might be lessened125, the burden of war would at best remain the same; there would be the same vast unproductive expenditure126, the same ruinous displacement of industry One result of the scheme might, in fact, defeat another. It is not altogether true in civil affairs that the strong man armed keeps his house in peace. The fact that he wears full armour127 is sometimes a source of quarrelsomeness, and a temptation to attack his neighbours.
The scheme of H. de Molinari failed to command the attention and interest which were essential to its serious consideration, because it was too large and ambitious. It was nevertheless founded, as it appears to me, on a correct principle, that, if war is ever to be arrested, it will be arrested by sacrifices on the part of those states which are neither at war nor desire to go to war. There is a very ancient example of this method of arresting and preventing the spread of war. Just before the dawn of Greek history, eve have a glimpse of the existence of several combinations of Greek tribes (which as yet can scarcely be called states) for the purpose of preventing war among themselves and resisting attacks from outside. Of these 'amphiktiones,' alliances of neighbouring communities clustered round a temple as a sanctuary128, one only constituted on a respectable scale survived to historical time, evidently in a state of decay, and liable to become the tool of any aggressive military Power, but still even then greatly venerated129. Now let us look around the world of our day, and try to see whether we can find anywhere an example of a successful amphiktiony, a combination of neighbouring Powers formed for the purpose of preventing wars.
I think we have seen for ten years or thereabouts a curiously130 similar alliance of the sort, framed for a similar purpose. I refer to the alliance of the three great sovereigns of Eastern Europe which is sometimes called the alliance of the three Emperors, which, however, they themselves do not admit to be in form more than a personal understanding. This alliance or understanding, if we may judge by the newspapers, is not particularly popular in Western Europe. Perhaps we do it the same injustice131, and for the same reason, which as historical students we do to such great territorial132 aggregates133 as the Medo-Persian Empire under the Great King. Political freedom and the movement which we call progress do not flourish in these vast territorial sovereignties, perhaps through some necessity of human nature; and thus we contrast them unfavourably with the Athenian Republic, the parent of art, science, and political liberty, or else with those modern societies to which we ourselves eminently134 belong. There is not much constitutionalism, as we understand the word, in Germany and Austro-Hungary, and there is none at all in Russia, and thus eve are led to forget the services they render to mankind by the maintenance of peace and the prevention of bloodshed.
I suppose that, of the causes of war which we know to exist in our day, there were never so many combined as in Eastern Europe during the last ten years. The antecedents of the three combined Emperors revere135 such as to threaten an outbreak of hostilities136 at any moment. Germany had ravaged137 a successful war against Austria, and also had inflicted138 bitter humiliation139 on France, till the other day the most powerful military state in Europe. Russia in 1877-8 had been at war with the Turkish Empire, which, though in the greatest decrepitude140, exercised a nominal141 sovereignty over nearly all of Eastern Europe which was not included in the dominions142 of the allied143 sovereigns. Among the small communities which were broken fragments of this Empire, the modern springs of war were in perpetual activity. The spirit of ambition, the spirit of religious antagonism144, the spirit of race combination or of nationality (whatever it has to be called), were all loose. Nevertheless, under these menacing conditions, the 'amphiktiony' of the three Empires preserved the peace. We do not know what were the exact terms of the understanding, nor do we quite know when it began. There are signs of something like it having existed before the Treaty of Berlin in 1878; and though it has to contend with many difficulties (at this moment with one most dangerous in Bulgaria), it is still said to exist. We cannot doubt what the main heads of the understanding must be. The three Emperors must have agreed to keep the peace among themselves, to resist the solicitations of external Powers, and to forget many of their own recollections. They must have aimed at keeping the quarrelsome little communities about them to the limits assigned to them by the Berlin Treaty. They have not absolutely succeeded in this; but, considering the difficulties, the success of the alliance has been conspicuous.
The precedent is one on which anyone who shares the hopes of the founder30 of this Professorship is forced to set the greatest store. It has been shown that a limited number of states, by isolating145 a limited group of questions, and agreeing to do their best (if necessary, by force) to prevent these questions from kindling146 the fire of belligerency, may preserve peace in a part of the world which seemed threatened by imminent147 war. It is not a very large experiment, but it has demanded sacrifices both of money and sentiment. It points to a method of abating148 war which in our day is novel, but which, after having had for about ten years the sanction of one precedent, is now in course of obtaining the sanction of another. For the alliance of the three Emperors is about to be succeeded by the combination of the Austro-Hungarian and German Governments with the Government of Italy. If, then, for periods of ten years together, one community or more, eager for war, can be prevented from engaging in it, one long step will have been taken towards the establishment of that permanent universal peace which has been hitherto a dream.
War is too huge and too ancient an evil for there to be much probability that it will submit to any one or any isolated149 panacea150. I would even say that there is a strong presumption151 against any system of treatment which promises to put a prompt and complete end to it. But, like those terrible conflagrations152 to which it has often been compared, it may perhaps be extinguished by local isolation153. In one instance at least, when apparently on the point of bursting out in a most inflammable structure, it has hitherto been kept under
1
pro
![]() |
|
n.赞成,赞成的意见,赞成者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2
abate
![]() |
|
vi.(风势,疼痛等)减弱,减轻,减退 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3
briefly
![]() |
|
adv.简单地,简短地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4
uncommonly
![]() |
|
adv. 稀罕(极,非常) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5
abated
![]() |
|
减少( abate的过去式和过去分词 ); 减去; 降价; 撤消(诉讼) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6
adoption
![]() |
|
n.采用,采纳,通过;收养 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7
mere
![]() |
|
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8
calumnies
![]() |
|
n.诬蔑,诽谤,中伤(的话)( calumny的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9
influential
![]() |
|
adj.有影响的,有权势的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10
humane
![]() |
|
adj.人道的,富有同情心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11
distinguished
![]() |
|
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12
hatred
![]() |
|
n.憎恶,憎恨,仇恨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13
inevitable
![]() |
|
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14
irreconcilable
![]() |
|
adj.(指人)难和解的,势不两立的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15
Christian
![]() |
|
adj.基督教徒的;n.基督教徒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16
doctrine
![]() |
|
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17
sect
![]() |
|
n.派别,宗教,学派,派系 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18
commemorated
![]() |
|
v.纪念,庆祝( commemorate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19
bestows
![]() |
|
赠给,授予( bestow的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20
professes
![]() |
|
声称( profess的第三人称单数 ); 宣称; 公开表明; 信奉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21
partisans
![]() |
|
游击队员( partisan的名词复数 ); 党人; 党羽; 帮伙 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22
conscientious
![]() |
|
adj.审慎正直的,认真的,本着良心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23
lawfulness
![]() |
|
法制,合法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24
martyr
![]() |
|
n.烈士,殉难者;vt.杀害,折磨,牺牲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25
contention
![]() |
|
n.争论,争辩,论战;论点,主张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26
Christians
![]() |
|
n.基督教徒( Christian的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27
sects
![]() |
|
n.宗派,教派( sect的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28
estranged
![]() |
|
adj.疏远的,分离的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29
followers
![]() |
|
追随者( follower的名词复数 ); 用户; 契据的附面; 从动件 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30
Founder
![]() |
|
n.创始者,缔造者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31
founders
![]() |
|
n.创始人( founder的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32
vehemently
![]() |
|
adv. 热烈地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33
immediate
![]() |
|
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34
spoke
![]() |
|
n.(车轮的)辐条;轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 v.讲,谈(speak的过去式);说;演说;从某种观点来说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35
apparently
![]() |
|
adv.显然地;表面上,似乎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36
hesitation
![]() |
|
n.犹豫,踌躇 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37
specially
![]() |
|
adv.特定地;特殊地;明确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38
primitive
![]() |
|
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39
sweeping
![]() |
|
adj.范围广大的,一扫无遗的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40
abolition
![]() |
|
n.废除,取消 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41
controversies
![]() |
|
争论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42
arbitration
![]() |
|
n.调停,仲裁 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43
defer
![]() |
|
vt.推迟,拖延;vi.(to)遵从,听从,服从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44
demur
![]() |
|
v.表示异议,反对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45
worthy
![]() |
|
adj.(of)值得的,配得上的;有价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46
ail
![]() |
|
v.生病,折磨,苦恼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47
applied
![]() |
|
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48
passionate
![]() |
|
adj.热情的,热烈的,激昂的,易动情的,易怒的,性情暴躁的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49
displacement
![]() |
|
n.移置,取代,位移,排水量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50
impeachable
![]() |
|
adj.可控告的,可弹劾的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51
underlies
![]() |
|
v.位于或存在于(某物)之下( underlie的第三人称单数 );构成…的基础(或起因),引起 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52
arbitrations
![]() |
|
n.仲裁,公断( arbitration的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53
contemplated
![]() |
|
adj. 预期的 动词contemplate的过去分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54
enthusiasts
![]() |
|
n.热心人,热衷者( enthusiast的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55
skilful
![]() |
|
(=skillful)adj.灵巧的,熟练的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56
eminent
![]() |
|
adj.显赫的,杰出的,有名的,优良的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57
celebrity
![]() |
|
n.名人,名流;著名,名声,名望 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58
obedience
![]() |
|
n.服从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59
irresistible
![]() |
|
adj.非常诱人的,无法拒绝的,无法抗拒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60
litigant
![]() |
|
n.诉讼当事人;adj.进行诉讼的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61
litigants
![]() |
|
n.诉讼当事人( litigant的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62
inquiry
![]() |
|
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63
judicial
![]() |
|
adj.司法的,法庭的,审判的,明断的,公正的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64
contrived
![]() |
|
adj.不自然的,做作的;虚构的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65
apprehension
![]() |
|
n.理解,领悟;逮捕,拘捕;忧虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66
functionaries
![]() |
|
n.公职人员,官员( functionary的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67
treatises
![]() |
|
n.专题著作,专题论文,专著( treatise的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68
affected
![]() |
|
adj.不自然的,假装的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69
jurisdiction
![]() |
|
n.司法权,审判权,管辖权,控制权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70
precedent
![]() |
|
n.先例,前例;惯例;adj.在前的,在先的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71
acquiesced
![]() |
|
v.默认,默许( acquiesce的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72
permanently
![]() |
|
adv.永恒地,永久地,固定不变地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73
defective
![]() |
|
adj.有毛病的,有问题的,有瑕疵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74
conspicuous
![]() |
|
adj.明眼的,惹人注目的;炫耀的,摆阔气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75
depredations
![]() |
|
n.劫掠,毁坏( depredation的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76
shipping
![]() |
|
n.船运(发货,运输,乘船) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77
questionable
![]() |
|
adj.可疑的,有问题的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78
analogous
![]() |
|
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79
uncertainty
![]() |
|
n.易变,靠不住,不确知,不确定的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80
condemn
![]() |
|
vt.谴责,指责;宣判(罪犯),判刑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81
condemned
![]() |
|
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82
breach
![]() |
|
n.违反,不履行;破裂;vt.冲破,攻破 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83
breaches
![]() |
|
破坏( breach的名词复数 ); 破裂; 缺口; 违背 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84
penally
![]() |
|
adv.与刑罚有关地;用刑罚,刑事上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85
omissions
![]() |
|
n.省略( omission的名词复数 );删节;遗漏;略去或漏掉的事(或人) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86
maritime
![]() |
|
adj.海的,海事的,航海的,近海的,沿海的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87
calamity
![]() |
|
n.灾害,祸患,不幸事件 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88
reactionary
![]() |
|
n.反动者,反动主义者;adj.反动的,反动主义的,反对改革的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89
expedients
![]() |
|
n.应急有效的,权宜之计的( expedient的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90
appreciable
![]() |
|
adj.明显的,可见的,可估量的,可觉察的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91
corporate
![]() |
|
adj.共同的,全体的;公司的,企业的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92
referees
![]() |
|
n.裁判员( referee的名词复数 );证明人;公断人;(专业性强的文章的)审阅人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93
afflicts
![]() |
|
使受痛苦,折磨( afflict的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94
violation
![]() |
|
n.违反(行为),违背(行为),侵犯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95
defiance
![]() |
|
n.挑战,挑衅,蔑视,违抗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96
offender
![]() |
|
n.冒犯者,违反者,犯罪者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97
diffused
![]() |
|
散布的,普及的,扩散的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98
repudiate
![]() |
|
v.拒绝,拒付,拒绝履行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99
restrictions
![]() |
|
约束( restriction的名词复数 ); 管制; 制约因素; 带限制性的条件(或规则) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100
naval
![]() |
|
adj.海军的,军舰的,船的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101
liberate
![]() |
|
v.解放,使获得自由,释出,放出;vt.解放,使获自由 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102
amicable
![]() |
|
adj.和平的,友好的;友善的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103
receded
![]() |
|
v.逐渐远离( recede的过去式和过去分词 );向后倾斜;自原处后退或避开别人的注视;尤指问题 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104
incurs
![]() |
|
遭受,招致,引起( incur的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105
perfidious
![]() |
|
adj.不忠的,背信弃义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106
persistently
![]() |
|
ad.坚持地;固执地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107
auxiliary
![]() |
|
adj.辅助的,备用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108
lamentable
![]() |
|
adj.令人惋惜的,悔恨的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109
wrought
![]() |
|
v.引起;以…原料制作;运转;adj.制造的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110
determined
![]() |
|
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111
contagion
![]() |
|
n.(通过接触的疾病)传染;蔓延 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112
interfere
![]() |
|
v.(in)干涉,干预;(with)妨碍,打扰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113
commonwealth
![]() |
|
n.共和国,联邦,共同体 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114
promotion
![]() |
|
n.提升,晋级;促销,宣传 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115
codification
![]() |
|
n.法典编纂,法律成文化;法规汇编 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116
undertaking
![]() |
|
n.保证,许诺,事业 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117
momentary
![]() |
|
adj.片刻的,瞬息的;短暂的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118
economist
![]() |
|
n.经济学家,经济专家,节俭的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119
belligerent
![]() |
|
adj.好战的,挑起战争的;n.交战国,交战者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120
thwart
![]() |
|
v.阻挠,妨碍,反对;adj.横(断的) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121
hostility
![]() |
|
n.敌对,敌意;抵制[pl.]交战,战争 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122
embody
![]() |
|
vt.具体表达,使具体化;包含,收录 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123
justification
![]() |
|
n.正当的理由;辩解的理由 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124
mechanism
![]() |
|
n.机械装置;机构,结构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125
lessened
![]() |
|
减少的,减弱的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126
expenditure
![]() |
|
n.(时间、劳力、金钱等)支出;使用,消耗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127
armour
![]() |
|
(=armor)n.盔甲;装甲部队 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128
sanctuary
![]() |
|
n.圣所,圣堂,寺庙;禁猎区,保护区 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129
venerated
![]() |
|
敬重(某人或某事物),崇敬( venerate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130
curiously
![]() |
|
adv.有求知欲地;好问地;奇特地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131
injustice
![]() |
|
n.非正义,不公正,不公平,侵犯(别人的)权利 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132
territorial
![]() |
|
adj.领土的,领地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133
aggregates
![]() |
|
数( aggregate的名词复数 ); 总计; 骨料; 集料(可成混凝土或修路等用的) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134
eminently
![]() |
|
adv.突出地;显著地;不寻常地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135
revere
![]() |
|
vt.尊崇,崇敬,敬畏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136
hostilities
![]() |
|
n.战争;敌意(hostility的复数);敌对状态;战事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137
ravaged
![]() |
|
毁坏( ravage的过去式和过去分词 ); 蹂躏; 劫掠; 抢劫 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138
inflicted
![]() |
|
把…强加给,使承受,遭受( inflict的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139
humiliation
![]() |
|
n.羞辱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140
decrepitude
![]() |
|
n.衰老;破旧 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141
nominal
![]() |
|
adj.名义上的;(金额、租金)微不足道的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142
dominions
![]() |
|
统治权( dominion的名词复数 ); 领土; 疆土; 版图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143
allied
![]() |
|
adj.协约国的;同盟国的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144
antagonism
![]() |
|
n.对抗,敌对,对立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145
isolating
![]() |
|
adj.孤立的,绝缘的v.使隔离( isolate的现在分词 );将…剔出(以便看清和单独处理);使(某物质、细胞等)分离;使离析 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146
kindling
![]() |
|
n. 点火, 可燃物 动词kindle的现在分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147
imminent
![]() |
|
adj.即将发生的,临近的,逼近的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148
abating
![]() |
|
减少( abate的现在分词 ); 减去; 降价; 撤消(诉讼) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149
isolated
![]() |
|
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150
panacea
![]() |
|
n.万灵药;治百病的灵药 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151
presumption
![]() |
|
n.推测,可能性,冒昧,放肆,[法律]推定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152
conflagrations
![]() |
|
n.大火(灾)( conflagration的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153
isolation
![]() |
|
n.隔离,孤立,分解,分离 | |
参考例句: |
|
|